SCALIA, J.,
Concurring in Part, Dissenting in Part
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
492 U.S. 302
Penry v. Lynaugh
CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES
COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE FIFTH CIRCUIT
No. 87-6177
Argued: January 11, 1989 --- Decided:
June 26, 1989
JUSTICE SCALIA, with
whom THE CHIEF JUSTICE, JUSTICE WHITE, and JUSTICE KENNEDY join,
concurring in part and dissenting in part.
I
I join Part I of the Court's opinion,
setting forth the facts and procedural history of this case; Part II-A,
holding that Teague v. Lane, 489 U.S. 288 (1989), which precludes
collateral [p351] relief that would
establish a "new rule," applies to capital sentencing; and Part IV-A,
holding that the exception to Teague for a new rule that places
certain matters "‘beyond the power of the criminal law-making authority,'"
id. at 311, quoting Mackey v. United States, 401 U.S. 667,
692 (1971) (separate opinion of Harlan, J.), applies to petitioner's
contention that the Eighth Amendment forbids the execution of mentally
retarded offenders. I also join Part IV-B, rejecting the latter
contention on the ground that execution of mentally retarded offenders
contravenes neither those practices condemned at the time the Bill of
Rights was adopted nor the "evolving standards of decency that mark the
progress of a maturing society." Trop v. Dulles, 356 U.S. 86, 101
(1958) (plurality opinion). Unlike JUSTICE O'CONNOR, however, I think we
need go no further to resolve the Eighth Amendment issue. Part IV-C of
her opinion goes on to examine whether application of the death penalty
to mentally retarded offenders
violates the Eighth Amendment
because it "makes no measurable contribution to acceptable goals of
punishment, and hence is nothing more than the purposeless and
needless imposition of pain and suffering" or because it is "grossly
out of proportion to the severity of the crime."
Ante at 335 (citations
omitted). For the reasons explained by the plurality in Stanford v.
Kentucky, post p. 361, I think this inquiry has no place in our
Eighth Amendment jurisprudence. "The punishment is either ‘cruel and
unusual' (i.e., society has set its face against it) or it is not."
Post at 378 (emphasis in original). If it is not unusual, that is,
if an objective examination of laws and jury determinations fails to
demonstrate society's disapproval of it, the punishment is not
unconstitutional even if out of accord with the theories of penology
favored by the Justices of this Court. See post at 379.
II
I disagree with the holding in Part
II-B of the Court's opinion that petitioner's contention, that his
sentencing was [p352] unconstitutional
because the Texas jury was not permitted fully to consider and give
effect to the mitigating evidence of his mental retardation and
background of abuse, does not seek the application of a "new rule," and
is therefore not barred by Teague. I also disagree with the
disposition of the merits of this contention, in Part III of the Court's
opinion.
A
The merits of this mitigation issue,
and the question whether, in raising it on habeas, petitioner seeks
application of a "new rule" within the meaning of Teague, are
obviously interrelated. I will say only a few words addressed
exclusively to the latter. Our holding in Teague rested upon the
historic role of habeas corpus in our system of law, which is to provide
a "deterrence,"
"the threat of [which] serves as
a necessary additional incentive for trial and appellate courts
throughout the land to conduct their proceedings in a manner
consistent with established constitutional standards."
489 U.S. at 306, quoting Desist
v. United States, 394 U.S. 244, 262-263 (1969) (Harlan, J.,
dissenting). "Deterrence" and "threat" are meaningless concepts as
applied to a situation in which the law is so uncertain that a judge
acting in all good faith and with the greatest of care could reasonably
read our precedents as permitting the result the habeas petitioner
contends is wrong. Thus, a "new rule," for purposes of Teague,
must include not only a new rule that replaces an old one, but a new
rule that replaces palpable uncertainty as to what the rule might be. We
acknowledged as much in Teague (in a passage given lip-service by
the Court today, see ante at 314) when we said that "a case
announces a new rule if the result was not dictated by precedent
existing at the time the defendant's conviction became final." 489 U.S.
at 301.
As my discussion of the merits will
make plain, it challenges the imagination to think that today's result
is "dictated" by our prior cases. Indeed, if there is any available
[p353] contention that our prior cases
compelled a particular result, it is the contention that
petitioner's claim was considered and rejected by Jurek v. Texas,
428 U.S. 262 (1976). Even if that contention is rejected, however, there
is no basis for finding a compulsion in the opposite direction. It seems
to me utterly impossible to say that a judge acting in good faith and
with care should have known the rule announced today, and that future
fault similar to that of which the Texas courts have been guilty must be
deterred by making good on the "threat" of habeas corpus.
In a system based on precedent and
stare decisis, it is the tradition to find each decision "inherent"
in earlier cases (however well concealed its presence might have been),
and rarely to replace a previously announced rule with a new one. If
Teague does not apply to a claimed "inherency" as vague and
debatable as that in the present case, then it applies only to habeas
requests for plain overruling -- which means that it adds little if
anything to the principles already in place concerning the retroactivity
of new rules in criminal cases, which provide that "a decision
announcing a new standard ‘is almost automatically nonretroactive' where
the decision ‘has explicitly overruled past precedent.'" Allen v.
Hardy, 478 U.S. 255, 258 (1986), quoting Solem v. Stumes, 465
U.S. 638, 646, 647 (1984). It is rare that a principle of law as
significant as that in Teague is adopted and gutted in the same
Term.
B
I turn next to the merits of
petitioner's mitigation claim. In Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238
(1972), we invalidated Georgia's capital punishment scheme on the ground
that, since there were no standards as to when it would be applied for a
particular crime, it created too great a risk that the death penalty
would be irrationally imposed. Four years later, however, we struck down
the capital sentencing schemes of North Carolina and Louisiana for the
opposite vice -- because they unduly constricted sentencing
discretion [p354] by failing to allow for
individualized consideration of the particular defendant and offense,
see Woodson v. North Carolina, 428 U.S. 280 (1976); Roberts v.
Louisiana, 428 U.S. 325 (1976). On the same day, however, we upheld
the schemes of Georgia, Texas, and Florida, because they struck the
proper balance, channeling the sentencer's discretion without unduly
restricting it. Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. 153 (1976); Jurek
v. Texas, supra; Proffitt v. Florida, 428 U.S. 242, 253 (1976). The
Texas system upheld in Jurek was precisely the same one the Court
finds unacceptable today, which structures the jury's discretion through
three questions relating to the defendant's personal culpability for the
crime, his future dangerousness, and the reasonableness of his response
to any provocation by the victim. In holding that this scheme
unconstitutionally limits the jury's discretion to consider the
mitigating evidence of Penry's mental retardation and abused childhood,
the Court today entirely disregards one of the two lines of our concern,
requiring individualized consideration to displace the channeling of
discretion, and throwing away Jurek in the process.
The Court contends that its
conclusion is not inconsistent with Jurek because that case
merely upheld a facial challenge to the Texas Special Issues framework.
According to the Court, it did not
preclud[e] a claim that, in a
particular case, the jury was unable to fully consider the mitigating
evidence introduced by a defendant in answering the special issues.
Ante at 321. I disagree.
While rejection of a facial challenge to a statute does not preclude all
as-applied attacks, surely it precludes one resting upon the same
asserted principle of law. And that is the situation here. The joint
opinion announcing the judgment in Jurek (it is necessary only to
describe the joint opinion, since the three Justices subscribing to the
opinion of JUSTICE WHITE, 428 U.S. at 277, would have upheld the Texas
statute on even broader grounds) said that "the constitutionality of the
Texas procedures turns on whether the enumerated questions allow
consideration of [p355] particularized
mitigating factors." Id. at 272. The claim that the Court
entertains and vindicates today flatly contradicts that analysis,
holding that the constitutionality turns on whether the questions allow
mitigating factors not only to be considered (and, of course, given
effect in answering the questions), but also to be given effect in
all possible ways, including ways that the questions do not permit.
It is simply not true that, as today's opinion asserts, the Jurek
Court had before it
the express assurance that the
special issues would permit the jury to fully consider all the
mitigating evidence a defendant introduced.
Ante at 321. What the Court
means by "fully consider" (what it must mean to distinguish
Jurek) is to consider for all purposes, including purposes not
specifically permitted by the questions. But there was no such
assurance at all. To the contrary, the portion of the Texas Court of
Criminal Appeals' opinion quoted in Jurek to evidence the
assurance began:
"In determining the likelihood
that the defendant would be a continuing threat to society [i.e.,
in considering the second question under the Texas statute], the jury
could consider . . . [,]"
428 U.S. at 272-273, quoting 522 S.W.2d
934, 939-940 (1975). The same focus upon the use of mitigating evidence
for the limited purpose of answering the enumerated questions, rather
than upon the jury's ability to use it for all purposes, is also evident
in the joint opinion's statement that
[the] Texas Court of Criminal
Appeals has not yet construed the first and third questions . . . ;
thus it is as yet undetermined whether or not the jury's
consideration of those questions would properly include
consideration of mitigating circumstances.
428 U.S. at 272, n. 7 (emphasis
added).
In short, it could not be clearer
that Jurek adopted the constitutional rule that the instructions
had to render all mitigating circumstances relevant to the jury's
verdict, but that the precise manner of their relevance -- the precise
effect of their consideration -- could be channeled by law. The
joint opinion approved the Texas statute expressly because it "focuses
the [p356] jury's objective consideration of
the particularized circumstances of the individual offense and the
individual offender." Id. at 274. Of course, there remains
available, in an as-applied challenge to the Texas statute, the
contention that a particular mitigating circumstance is in fact
irrelevant to any of the three questions it poses, and hence could not
be considered. But that is not the case here, nor is it the ground upon
which the Court relies. Special Issue One required the jury to determine
whether
the conduct of the defendant
that caused the death of the deceased was committed deliberately and
with the reasonable expectation that the death of the deceased or
another would result.
Ante at 310. As the plurality
observed in Franklin v. Lynaugh, 487 U.S. 164 (1988),
[t]he Texas courts have
consistently held that something more must be found in the penalty
phase -- something beyond the guilt-phase finding of "intentional"
commission of the crime -- before the jury can determine that a
capital murder is "deliberate" within the meaning of the first Special
Issue.
Id. at 171-175 (citing Texas
cases). Evidence of Penry's mental retardation and abused childhood was
relevant to that point. He was permitted to introduce all that evidence,
relied upon it in urging the jury to answer "no" to the Special Issues,
and had the benefit of an instruction specifically telling the jury to
consider all evidence for that purpose. See App. 26. Thus, the
only available contention here, and the basis on which the Court decides
the case, is that this evidence "has relevance to . . . moral
culpability beyond the scope of the special issues." Ante at 322.
That contention was considered and rejected by Jurek's holding
that the statute's "focus[ing of] the jury's objective consideration"
was constitutional. 428 U.S. at 274.
But even if petitioner's claim is
not foreclosed by Jurek, the Court clearly errs in asserting that
our later precedents "compe[l]" the conclusion that it is valid, ante
at 328. While it is true that our cases have held that "a death penalty
statute must not preclude consideration of relevant mitigating
[p357] factors," including "any aspect of a
defendant's character or record and any of the circumstances of the
offense," Lockett v. Ohio, 438 U.S. 586, 604, 608, (1978); see
also Eddings v. Oklahoma, 455 U.S. 104, 110-112 (1982), we have
never held that "the State has no role in structuring or giving shape to
the jury's consideration of these mitigating factors." Franklin,
487 U.S. at 179. As JUSTICE STEVENS pointed out in Barclay v.
Florida, 463 U.S. 939 (1983), neither Lockett nor Eddings
establish[ed] the weight which
must be given to any particular mitigating evidence, or the manner in
which it must be considered; they simply condemn any procedure in
which such evidence has no weight at all.
Id. at 961, n. 2 (opinion
concurring in judgment). See also Zant v. Stephens, 462 U.S. 862,
875-876, n. 13 (1983) ("[S]pecific standards for balancing aggravating
against mitigating circumstances are not constitutionally required").
We have held that a State may not
make the death penalty mandatory, see Sumner v. Shuman, 483 U.S.
66 (1987); Woodson, 428 U.S. 280 (1976); Roberts, 428 U.S.
325 (1976), and that it may not affirmatively preclude a sentencer from
considering mitigating evidence presented by a defendant, see
Hitchcock v. Dugger, 481 U.S. 393 (1987); Skipper v. South
Carolina, 476 U.S. 1 (1986). The sentences in Eddings and
Lockett, the cases upon which the Court principally relies, ran
afoul of the latter rule -- Eddings because the sentencing judge
thought Oklahoma law categorically prevented him from considering
certain mitigating evidence, and Lockett because Ohio law limited
the mitigating factors to three, which on their face would not embrace
even such rudimentary elements as lack of intent to kill the victim, the
defendant's comparatively minor role in the offense, and age. As we
noted in Jurek and the Court does not contest today, Texas
permits all mitigating factors to be considered, though only for
purposes of answering the three Special Issues (and there is no question
that the specific mitigation offered was relevant to at least one of
them). That is why the Lockett [p358]
Court found the Texas statute "significantly different" from the Ohio
scheme. 438 U.S. at 607. And that is why we have continued to say, after
Eddings and Lockett, that the Texas Special Issues
allo[w] the jury to consider the
mitigating aspects of the crime and the unique characteristics of the
perpetrator, and therefore sufficiently provid[e] for jury discretion.
Lowenfield v. Phelps, 484
U.S. 231, 245 (1988). See also Pulley v. Harris, 465 U.S. 37,
48-49 (1984); Zant v. Stephens, supra, at 875-876, n. 13;
Adams v. Texas, 448 U.S. 38, 46 (1980). I acknowledge that some
statements in Lockett and Eddings, read in isolation from
the facts of the cases, might be thought to establish the principle that
the Court today adopts. One must read cases, however, not in a vacuum,
but in light of their facts -- which, in conjunction with the clear and
constant reaffirmation of Jurek, leads to the conclusion that all
mitigating factors must be able to be considered by the sentencer, but
need not be able to be considered for all purposes.
Finally, I turn briefly to the place
of today's holding within the broad scheme of our constitutional
jurisprudence regarding capital sentencing, as opposed to the
immediately applicable precedents. It is out of order there as well. As
noted at the outset of this discussion, our law regarding capital
sentencing has sought to strike a balance between complete discretion,
which produces "wholly arbitrary and capricious action," Gregg,
428 U.S. at 189, and no discretion at all, which prevents the
individuating characteristics of the defendant and of the crime to be
taken into account, Woodson, supra, at 303-304. That is why, in
Jurek, we did not regard the Texas Special Issues as inherently
bad, but to the contrary thought them a desirable means of "focus[ing]
the jury's objective consideration of the particularized circumstances,"
428 U.S. at 274, or, as the plurality put it in Franklin, "channel[ing]
jury discretion . . . to achieve a more rational and equitable
administration of the death penalty," 487 U.S. at 181. In providing for
juries to consider all [p359] mitigating
circumstances insofar as they bear upon (1) deliberateness, (2) future
dangerousness, and (3) provocation, it seems to me Texas had adopted a
rational scheme that meets the two concerns of our Eighth Amendment
jurisprudence. The Court today demands that it be replaced, however,
with a scheme that simply dumps before the jury all sympathetic factors
bearing upon the defendant's background and character, and the
circumstances of the offense, so that the jury may decide without
further guidance whether he "lacked the moral culpability to be
sentenced to death," ante at 324, "did not deserve to be
sentenced to death," ante at 326, or "was not sufficiently
culpable to deserve the death penalty," ibid. The Court seeks to
dignify this by calling it a process that calls for a "reasoned moral
response," ante at 323, 328 -- but reason has nothing to do with
it, the Court having eliminated the structure that required reason. It
is an unguided, emotional "moral response" that the Court demands be
allowed -- an outpouring of personal reaction to all the circumstances
of a defendant's life and personality, an unfocused sympathy. Not only
have we never before said the Constitution requires this, but the line
of cases following Gregg sought to eliminate precisely the
unpredictability it produces. See, e. g., Godfrey v. Georgia, 446
U.S. 420, 428 (1980) (States "must channel the [capital] sentencer's
discretion by ‘clear and objective standards' that provide ‘specific and
detailed guidance,' and that ‘make rationally reviewable the process for
imposing a sentence of death'") (citations omitted); California v.
Brown, 479 U.S. 538, 541 (1987) ("[S]entencers may not be given
unbridled discretion in determining the fates of those charged with
capital offenses"; the "Constitution . . . requires that death penalty
statutes be structured so as to prevent the penalty from being
administered in an arbitrary and unpredictable fashion").
The Court cannot seriously believe
that rationality and predictability can be achieved, and capriciousness
avoided, by "‘narrow[ing] a sentencer's discretion to impose the
death [p360] sentence,'" but expanding his
discretion "‘to decline to impose the death sentence,'" ante
at 327, quoting McCleskey v. Kemp, 481 U.S. 279, 304 (1987) (emphasis
in original). The decision whether to impose the death penalty is a
unitary one; unguided discretion not to impose is unguided discretion to
impose as well. In holding that the jury had to be free to deem Penry's
mental retardation and sad childhood relevant for whatever purpose it
wished, the Court has come full circle, not only permitting but
requiring what Furman once condemned. "Freakishly" and "wantonly,"
Furman, 408 U.S. at 310 (Stewart, J. concurring), have been
rebaptized "reasoned moral response." I do not think the Constitution
forbids what the Court imposes here, but I am certain it does not
require it.
I respectfully dissent.
|